9.5.2—
An Objection: Metaphysical and "Nomological" Sufficiency
One concern I can expect this argument to raise would be that people interested in supervenience accounts tend to view the kind of sufficiency involved not as logical or metaphysical sufficiency, as I have assumed, but as something called "nomological sufficiency." I must confess to some puzzlement about what is meant by "nomological sufficiency." It must mean something more than material sufficiency, since materially sufficient conditions may be completely unrelated to what they are conditions for. If the tallest man who ever lived was in fact married to the first woman to climb Everest, and was her only husband, then being married to the first woman to climb Everest is materially sufficient for being the tallest man who ever lived. But surely nomological sufficiency amounts to more than this. Perhaps nomological sufficiency amounts to something like "material sufficiency in all possible worlds that have the same natural laws as the actual world." But, according to the thought
experiment above, the world described is like the actual world in all physical laws. If these assured that the psychophysical relationships must be the same the way fixing your statistical mechanics fixes your thermodynamics, we should be able to derive this fact the way we can do so in the case of thermodynamics. But this seems plainly to be impossible. It seems, then, that naturalistic conditions would not be nomologically sufficient for intentionality either. But perhaps nomological sufficiency does not apply to all worlds with natural laws like our own, but only ones specified by a certain counterfactual. But which counterfactual? And how do we know that a world like the one described above does not fall within the scope of it? Indeed, how does one know that the actual world meets the desired criterion? But perhaps nomological sufficiency is material sufficiency in all worlds sharing psycho physical laws with the actual world. This stipulation, however, would be inadmissible for two reasons. First, this violates the condition of strong naturalism that the relation be metaphysically necessary and epistemically transparent. Second, we do not know that the naturalistic criteria are met in the actual world.
Finally, let us be quite clear about separating the question of logical possibility from the question of warranted belief. No one is claiming that it is reasonable to believe that one is, for example, in the clutches of a Cartesian demon. And while some people do claim that there are nonmaterial thinking beings, their use in this kind of example is not based upon the likelihood of their existence, but upon their possibility. If one has an account of what it is to be in a meaningful mental state, it had better apply to all possible beings that could have such mental states. Regardless of the likelihood of Cartesian demons or nonembodied spirits, if they are possible, then an account of the nature of intentionality had best apply to them too.